Definition & Meaning | English word LOGICS


LOGICS

Definitions of LOGICS

  1. plural of logic.
  2. inflection of logic

Number of letters

6

Is palindrome

No

12
CS
GI
GIC
IC
ICS
LO
LOG
OG
OGI

2

22

25

194
CG
CGI
CGL
CGO
CGS
CI
CIG
CIL
CIO
CIS

Examples of Using LOGICS in a Sentence

  • In standard systems of classical logic, these connectives are interpreted as truth functions, though they receive a variety of alternative interpretations in nonclassical logics.
  • While not entailed by the preceding conditions, contemporary discussions of classical logic normally only include propositional and first-order logics.
  • His 2000 paper on the ambient calculus subject with Luca Cardelli, "Anytime, Anywhere: Modal Logics for Mobile Ambients", won the 2010 SIGPLAN Most Influential POPL Paper Award.
  • The paradox may be expressed in natural language and in various logics, including certain forms of set theory, lambda calculus, and combinatory logic.
  • HOL (Higher Order Logic) denotes a family of interactive theorem proving systems using similar (higher-order) logics and implementation strategies.
  • In data analytics, necessity and sufficiency can refer to different causal logics, where necessary condition analysis and qualitative comparative analysis can be used as analytical techniques for examining necessity and sufficiency of conditions for a particular outcome of interest.
  • There are general, spatial, temporal, spatiotemporal, and fuzzy description logics, and each description logic features a different balance between expressive power and reasoning complexity by supporting different sets of mathematical constructors.
  • BAN logic, and logics in the same family, are decidable: there exists an algorithm taking BAN hypotheses and a purported conclusion, and that answers whether or not the conclusion is derivable from the hypotheses.
  • This is contrasted with the more commonly known bivalent logics (such as classical sentential or Boolean logic) which provide only for true and false.
  • Higher-order logics do not directly apply classical logic to certain new sub-fields within philosophy but generalize it by allowing quantification not just over individuals but also over predicates.
  • The Lindenbaum algebra of most logics that support conjunction and disjunction is a distributive lattice, i.
  • Topological semantics is widely used in recent work in formal epistemology and has antecedents in earlier work such as David Lewis and Angelika Kratzer's logics for counterfactuals.
  • Most studied formal logics have a monotonic entailment relation, meaning that adding a formula to the hypotheses never produces a pruning of its set of conclusions.
  • The change of semantics that he proposed permits to provide a complete deductive calculus for type theory and for second-order logic, amongst other logics.
  • Scholars have argued that embedded liberalism (or the logics inherent in the Double Movement) are key to maintaining public support for the planks of the LIO; some scholars have raised questions whether aspects of embedded liberalism have been undermined, thus leading to a backlash against the LIO.
  • In substructural logics, typically premises are not composed into sets, but rather they are composed into more fine-grained structures, such as trees or multisets (sets that distinguish multiple occurrences of elements) or sequences of formulae.
  • Inconsistency-tolerant logics have been discussed since at least 1910 (and arguably much earlier, for example in the writings of Aristotle); however, the term paraconsistent ("beside the consistent") was first coined in 1976, by the Peruvian philosopher Francisco MirĂ³ Quesada Cantuarias.
  • In 1972, Sylvan (in a paper co-authored with Plumwood) proposed semantics for certain relevant logics that had been developed by American philosophers Nuel Belnap and Alan Ross Anderson.
  • Thus, philosophical logicians and formal semanticists have developed a wide variety of conditional logics that better match actual conditional language and conditional reasoning.
  • In classical logic and many modal logics, every formula can be brought into this form by replacing implications and equivalences by their definitions, using De Morgan's laws to push negation inwards, and eliminating double negations.
  • Higher-order logics include the offshoots of Church's simple theory of types and the various forms of intuitionistic type theory.
  • Other logical systems, however, do not explode in this manner when contradictions are introduced; such contradiction-tolerant systems are known as paraconsistent logics.
  • Interpretability logics and Japaridze's polymodal logic present natural extensions of provability logic.
  • Notions of compactness and completeness that are equivalent in finitary logic sometimes are not so in infinitary logics.
  • So-called deviant logics reject some of these basic intuitions and propose alternative rules governing the validity of arguments.



Search for LOGICS in:






Page preparation took: 404.55 ms.